Twenty-First Century

Twenty-First Century

Sustaining Engineering Codes of Ethics for the Twenty-First Century

Diane Michelfelder • Sharon A. Jones

Received: 7 April 2011 / Accepted: 6 September 2011 / Published online: 23 September 2011

� Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Abstract How much responsibility ought a professional engineer to have with regard to supporting basic principles of sustainable development? While within the

United States, professional engineering societies, as reflected in their codes of

ethics, differ in their responses to this question, none of these professional societies

has yet to put the engineer’s responsibility toward sustainability on a par with

commitments to public safety, health, and welfare. In this paper, we aim to suggest

that sustainability should be included in the paramountcy clause because it is a

necessary condition to ensure the safety, health, and welfare of the public. Part of

our justification rests on the fact that to engineer sustainably means among many

things to consider social justice, understood as the fair and equitable distribution of

social goods, as a design constraint similar to technical, economic, and environ-

mental constraints. This element of social justice is not explicit in the current

paramountcy clause. Our argument rests on demonstrating that social justice in

terms of both inter- and intra-generational equity is an important dimension of

sustainability (and engineering). We also propose that embracing sustainability in

the codes while recognizing the role that social justice plays may elevate the status

of the engineer as public intellectual and agent of social good. This shift will then

need to be incorporated in how we teach undergraduate engineering students about

engineering ethics.

Keywords Engineering codes of ethics � Engineering education � Paramountcy clause � Social justice � Sustainability

D. Michelfelder

Department of Philosophy, Macalester College, St. Paul, MN 55105, USA

e-mail: [email protected]

S. A. Jones (&) School of Engineering, University of Portland, Portland, OR 97203, USA

e-mail: [email protected]

123

Sci Eng Ethics (2013) 19:237–258

DOI 10.1007/s11948-011-9310-2

Introduction

The National Society for Professional Engineering (NSPE) revised its Code of

Ethics in 2007 to encourage engineers to ‘‘adhere to the principles of sustainable

development.’’ Similar organizations have stressed the need for engineers to support

these principles in the course of their professional practice. Further calls, however, for engineers to consider the related issue of social justice have met with

considerable debate over what such inclusion may mean for engineering codes of

ethics (Scherer 2003). For example, Vesilind (2002) claims that ‘‘engineers can,

while staying well within the bounds of the present Codes of Ethics, destroy or

modify the environments that support the global ecosystem and in such manner kill

future humans on a grand scale’’ (92). Others, though, have argued that while

sustainability can be ‘‘engineered,’’ justice is a separate societal goal beyond the

scope of the engineer (Agyeman and Evans 2003; Agyeman 2005). There is also the

question of whether the addition of sustainability to the codes of ethics is redundant:

i.e., does the fundamental canon for all professional engineers to ‘‘hold paramount

the public’s welfare’’ already include a commitment to sustainability and perhaps

social justice as well? Even those who agree that sustainability, justice, and the

fundamental canon are not redundant, see the first two issues as outside of the

paramountcy clause, thus devaluing such adherence in professional practice,

perhaps even to the point of making such adherence supererogatory.

Much of the debate described above centers around the relationship among

sustainability, justice, and public health and safety. By better understanding this

relationship, the NSPE and other professional engineering organizations can

appropriately incorporate sustainability into engineering codes of ethics, and thus

exert a positive influence on the practice of engineering. We recognize there are

many critiques of these codes in terms of their ability to affect the individual

engineer who is often faced with many conflicting goals related to project execution.

Some of these critiques are presented in Davis (2001), even as the author tries to

dispel them. While we acknowledge the existence of these critiques, the

implementation of the codes is not the subject of this paper. Instead, we intend to

further discussion, particularly among professional engineers, of what should be

included and prioritized within the codes. We aim to suggest that sustainability

should be included in the paramountcy clause because it is a necessary condition to

ensure the safety, health, and welfare of the public. Our argument rests on

demonstrating that social justice in terms of both inter- and intra-generational equity

is an important dimension of sustainability (and engineering). We also propose that

embracing sustainability in the codes while recognizing the role that social justice

plays may elevate the status of the engineer as public intellectual and agent of social

good. This shift will then need to be incorporated in how we teach undergraduate

engineering students about engineering ethics.

Calls for the engineering profession to deepen its commitments to sustainability

and social justice and proposals to rephrase engineering ethics codes to better reflect

such commitments have mounted in recent years (see for example Baillie and

Catalano 2009; Catalano 2006a, b; Riley 2008.) Our approach adds to these calls by

emphasizing the need to include sustainability in the paramountcy clause of the

238 D. Michelfelder, S. A. Jones

123

codes and by looking at social justice as a dimension of sustainability. We start our

discussion with an overview of what the term sustainability has come to mean, first

in terms of engineering codes of ethics and second, in terms of the engineering

profession itself. This overview demonstrates the uncertainties regarding how

sustainability currently meshes with engineering. We then show how the inclusion

of sustainability in the codes serves to address these uncertainties.

Sustainability and Engineering Codes of Ethics

The phrase ‘‘sustainable development’’ was formally added to the NSPE Code of

Ethics in 2007 and to ASCE’s code in 1996; however, it is missing from the codes

for the other traditional engineering professional organizations. And, both ASCE

and NSPE treat the term in different ways that affect its importance in terms of the

hierarchy of values within the codes.

The NSPE code includes six fundamental canons, followed by rules of practice

that provide guidance to engineers on how to adopt these canons as part of

professional practice. Neither the canons nor the rules of practice include any

reference to sustainability or to sustainable development. Instead, the six canons

stipulate the paramountcy clause in terms of the safety, health, and welfare of the

public, and refer to characteristics such as competency, loyalty, honor, reputation,

and honesty in the fulfillment of professional duties. Rounding out the NSPE code is

a list of nine professional obligations that, if adhered to, also help an engineer to

follow the code. Several professional obligations are closely tied to specific canons.

One of these nine professional obligations states that engineers shall at all times strive to serve the public interest. It is here that one finds the phrase engineers are encouraged to adhere to the principles of sustainable development, as one of four suggestions for how to accomplish this professional obligation. In other words,

according to the NSPE, while engineers are encouraged to ‘‘adhere to the principles

of sustainable development’’ so that they fulfill their obligation to ‘‘strive to serve

the public interest,’’ they are not required to follow these sustainability principles to

‘‘hold paramount the safety, health, and welfare of the public.’’ One is left to

conclude that NSPE does not view sustainable development as a necessary

condition for maintaining the public’s safety, health, and welfare.

ASCE uses the Accreditation Board for Engineering and Technology’s (ABET)

Code of Ethics as the framework for its own code. ASCE describes four

fundamental principles for civil engineers to follow to ensure compliance with the

canons, followed by the canons themselves, and then guidelines for how to practice

each canon. None of the four fundamental principles specifically includes

‘‘sustainability.’’ However, ASCE changed the canons in 1997 to include

sustainable development in the first and primary canon as follows: Engineers shall hold paramount the safety, health and welfare of the public and shall strive to comply with the principles of sustainable development in the performance of their professional duties. And in 2009, ASCE adopted the following definition of sustainable development: ‘‘Sustainable development is the process of applying natural, human, and economic resources to enhance the safety, welfare, and quality

Sustaining Engineering Codes of Ethics 239